Generally speaking, there are two ways the works of Soren Kierkegaard have been interpreted. The first, and more well-known, is to see him as a rather extreme religious existentialist thinker who placed blind faith as his top priority. According to this interpretation Kierkegaard believed that faith alone, unsupported by any historical or logical reasoning, is the ultimate criterion for judging a person’s existential value. His account of Abraham’s willingness to sacrifice his only son Isaac if asked to by God in Fear and Trembling clearly focuses this extreme view of religious faithfulness. The person of faith finds himself treading water over 70,000 fathoms still believing the impossible contradiction that God became human. In other words, it is a leap of faith, there is no basis for it.
The second way of interpreting Kierkegaard’s line of thought is to see it as simply absurd at the outset and thus necessarily dismissible from a rational, philosophical point of view. This is, to be sure, the predominant point of view of most philosophical, and even many theological, thinkers. Henry Allison, in his essay “Christianity and Nonsense”, argues that Johannes Climacus’ presentation of the logic of Christian faith in Kierkegaard’s Concluding Unscientific Postscript is either self-contradictory or flat-out irrational. (Cf. “Christianity and Nonsense” in Philosophy Today # 1) So we have this dilemma of how to understand Kierkegaard at the heart of his writings and perspective. Which way Kierkegaard?
I struggled with this issue for many years during my early years as a student of both philosophy and theology. I finally was able to put my mind to rest when I read Louis Mackey’s interpretation in his very insightful book Kierkegaard: A Kind of Poet. Mackey’s overview of Kierkegaard’s entire authorship revolves around his understanding of Kierkegaard as a poetic writer who, in and through his various writings and characters, “traffics in existential possibilities”. Rather than seeking to present a solid, one-dimensional perspective that covers all perspectives and interpretations of faith and life, Kierkegaard is, according to Mackey, striving to present the reader with a variety of perspectives embodied in the various characters comprising the cast of his creative writings in order to force the reader to think deeply and choose amongst them for him or herself.
Kierkegaard himself sets the stage for this way of viewing his authorship in his very early The Point of View for Understanding My Work as an Author and in his doctoral dissertation The Concept of Irony. In both of these works Kierkegaard extols the virtues of “indirect communication”, pseudonymity, and irony as the proper means of expressing and focusing of the various existential possibilities confronting the human individual. He makes it quite clear that his own works are to be understood as stimulators to one’s own action, not as patterns to be copied. I think there can be little doubt that in spite of numerous misunderstandings and exaggerations, Kierkegaard’s writings have succeeded achieving his goals. The characters and options populating his many works continue to be at the center of numerous lectures, debates, and writings, as well as the actual choices and behavioral patterns of those who have read his works.
Viewed from this interpretive perspective the many characters in Kierkegaard’s numerous volumes take on a whole new meaning and interest. Indeed, he himself becomes visible as more of a person in his own right rather than merely as a brilliant but eccentric theological thinker. So, I no longer struggle with the logical and theological issues raised by Kierkegaard’s writings in the same way as I used to. I still gather challenges and insights about my own way of being in the world, and still enjoy the cleverness of both the author and his characters, but I no longer puzzle over the confusing and at times seeming contradictory character of his incredible literary quality and theological diatribes. Actually, he now seems even more creative and insightful than before I came to understand him as primarily a literary artist. I would be very interested to know if and how any of these thoughts may strike my readers. (L. Mackey: Kierkegaard: A Kind of Poet, W. Lowrie, A Short Life of Kierkegaard, J. Gill, Essays on Kierkegaard)
One response to “Which Way Kierkegaard?”
Yes, as in “Either/Or”, SK is not himself at the aesthetic, ethical, or religious stage of life. If anything, he is in permanent infinite resignation. He is pointing out the nodes of the human existential dynamic, though I think his concept of authenticity in moral action leaves much to be desired and has not been adequately interpreted by Heidegger, Sartre, or Wild.